March 14, 2005
Caplan on time preference

Bryan Caplan at EconLog last week criticized what he called the “myth” of Misesian “time preference” theory.

Problem #1 with Bryan’s critique: there are at least two senses of “time preference”. Bryan starts out with a quote from Mises that expresses what we might call the idea of “absence of categorical time indifference”: the idea that, if we see you consuming now, you must not be indifferent at every margin between consuming now and consuming indefinitely later. Bryan rightly observes that diminishing marginal utility over dated consumption is sufficient to explain why all consumption is not indefinitely postponed. What Bryan doesn’t see is that DMU is consistent with Mises’s view, not a contradiction of it. (Mises was, in fact, a pioneer in explaining diminishing marginal utility in ordinalist terms.)

Problem #2: Bryan seems to think that the scarcity of present goods, relative to future goods (in a world of positive growth, obviously) is a sufficient explanation for the premium on present goods. He offers an analogy:

Gold has (almost?) always been more expensive than silver, but we don't need to postulate "gold preference" to explain this pattern. The greater scarcity of gold is all the explanation we need.

If we were to take this line seriously, we would eliminate the subjectivist revolution in economics: any relative price can be explained by scarcity (read: real cost) without reference to preferences!

It can be imagined (although I doubt that it’s true) that people have the same preferences for gold as for silver, only the world happens to be more abundantly endowed with silver. The problem with considering this case analogous to present and future goods is that the greater abundance of future goods isn’t a happenstance. It’s endogenous, the result of our saving and investment practices. Future goods are not manna from heaven. But a world where future income is exogenous seems to be exactly the world Bryan imagines:

Suppose we knew the price of food would double next year. Then a pound of food now trades for half a pound of food one year from now. Translation: a negative 50% interest rate! If this seems crazy to you, suppose food were the only commodity, and you expect a famine next year. Wouldn't you happily trade 2 pounds of current food in exchange for a promissory note good for 1 pound of food next year?

Bryan rightly points out that growing income “gives even perfectly patient people a reason to increase their demand for current consumption.” That is, even a person who is indifferent between an extra dollar today and an extra dollar tomorrow, when today and tomorrow are equally provisioned, will prefer the extra dollar today when tomorrow is already better provisioned.
Bryan then concludes:

Of course, none of this means that time preference does not exist. It does. But you don't need it to explain the existence of interest. Diminishing marginal utility does that job.

No, DMU doesn’t do that job at all. DMU doesn’t explain why, even when today and tomorrow are equally provisioned, the market characteristically values a dollar today higher than a dollar tomorrow. That’s a fact that we need time preference to explain.

Posted by Lawrence H. White at 11:13 AM in Economics  ·  TrackBack (35)

The statesman who should attempt to direct private people in what manner they ought to employ their capitals would not only load himself with a most unnecessary attention, but assume an authority which could safely be trusted, not only to no single person, but to no council or senate whatever, and which would nowhere be so dangerous as in the hands of a man who had folly and presumption enough to fancy himself fit to exercise it. -Adam Smith

Our Bloggers
Joshua Hall
Robert Lawson
E. Frank Stephenson
Michael C. Munger
Lawrence H. White
Craig Depken
Tim Shaughnessy
Edward J. Lopez
Brad Smith
Mike DeBow
Wilson Mixon
Art Carden
Noel Campbell

Search

Archives
By Author:
Joshua Hall
Robert Lawson
E. Frank Stephenson
Michael C. Munger
Lawrence H. White
Edward Bierhanzl
Craig Depken
Ralph R. Frasca
Tim Shaughnessy
Edward J. Lopez
Brad Smith
Mike DeBow
Wilson Mixon
Art Carden
Noel Campbell

By Month:
February 2014
November 2013
October 2013
September 2013
August 2013
July 2013
June 2013
May 2013
April 2013
March 2013
February 2013
January 2013
December 2012
November 2012
October 2012
September 2012
August 2012
July 2012
June 2012
May 2012
April 2012
March 2012
February 2012
January 2012
December 2011
November 2011
October 2011
September 2011
August 2011
July 2011
June 2011
May 2011
April 2011
March 2011
February 2011
January 2011
December 2010
November 2010
October 2010
September 2010
August 2010
July 2010
June 2010
May 2010
April 2010
March 2010
February 2010
January 2010
December 2009
November 2009
October 2009
September 2009
August 2009
July 2009
June 2009
May 2009
April 2009
March 2009
February 2009
January 2009
December 2008
November 2008
October 2008
September 2008
August 2008
July 2008
June 2008
May 2008
April 2008
March 2008
February 2008
January 2008
December 2007
November 2007
October 2007
September 2007
August 2007
July 2007
June 2007
May 2007
April 2007
March 2007
February 2007
January 2007
December 2006
November 2006
October 2006
September 2006
August 2006
July 2006
June 2006
May 2006
April 2006
March 2006
February 2006
January 2006
December 2005
November 2005
October 2005
September 2005
August 2005
July 2005
June 2005
May 2005
April 2005
March 2005
February 2005
January 2005
December 2004
November 2004
October 2004
September 2004
August 2004
July 2004

Powered by
Movable Type 2.661

Site design by
Sekimori

XML